Go Back   I-Mockery Forum > I-Mockery Discussion Forums > Philosophy, Politics, and News
FAQ Members List Calendar Today's Posts

Reply
 
Thread Tools Display Modes
  #1  
The One and Only... The One and Only... is offline
Mocker
The One and Only...'s Avatar
Join Date: Jun 2003
Location: Harlem
The One and Only... is probably a spambot
Old Aug 5th, 2005, 02:49 PM        Kant, Mises, and Economics - An interesting read
Source: http://www.mises.org/esandtam/pes1.asp

Economic Science and the Austrian Method Hans-Herman Hoppe

PRAXEOLOGY AND
ECONOMIC SCIENCE

It is well-known that Austrians disagree strongly with other schools of economic thought, such as the Keynesians, the Monetarists, the Public Choicers, Historicists, Institutionalists, and Marxists. [1] Disagreement is most conspicuous, of course, when it comes to economic policy and economic policy proposals. At times there also exists an alliance between Austrians and, in particular, Chicagoites and Public Choicers. Ludwig von Mises, Murray N. Rothbard, Milton Friedman, and James Buchanan, to cite a few names, are often united in their efforts to defend the free market economy against its "liberal" and socialist detractors.

Nonetheless, as important as such occasional agreements may be for tactical or strategic reasons, they can only be superficial, for they cover up some truly fundamental differences between the Austrian school, as represented by Mises and Rothbard, and all the rest. The ultimate difference from which all disagreements at the levels of economic theory and economic policy —disagreements, for instance, as regards the merit of the gold standard vs. fiat money, free-banking vs. central banking, the welfare implications of markets vs. state-action, capitalism vs. socialism, the theory of interest and the business cycle, etc.—concerns the answer to the very first question that any economist must raise: What is the subject matter of economics, and what kind of propositions are economic theorems?

Mises's answer is that economics is the science of human action. In itself, this may not sound very controversial. But then Mises says of the science of economics:

Its statements and propositions are not derived from experience. They are, like those of logic and mathematics, a priori. They are not subject to verification and falsification on the ground of experience and facts. They are both logically and temporally antecedent to any comprehension of historical facts. They are a necessary requirement of any intellectual grasp of historical events. [2]

In order to emphasize the status of economics as a pure science, a science that has more in common with a discipline like applied logic than, for instance, with the empirical natural sciences, Mises proposes the term "praxeology" (the logic of action) for the branch of knowledge exemplified by economics. [3]

It is this assessment of economics as an a priori science, a science whose propositions can be given a rigorous logical justification, which distinguishes Austrians, or more precisely Misesians, from all other current economic schools. All the others conceive of economics as an empirical science, as a science like physics, which develops hypotheses that require continual empirical testing. And they all regard as dogmatic and unscientific Mises's view that economic theorems—like the law of marginal utility, or the law of returns, or the time-preference theory of interest and the Austrian business cycle theory—can be given definite proof, such that it can be shown to be plainly contradictory to deny their validity.

The view of Mark Blaug, highly representative of mainstream methodological thought, illustrates this almost universal opposition to Austrianism. Blaug says of Mises, "His writings on the foundations of economic science are so cranky and idiosyncratic that one can only wonder that they have been taken seriously by anyone." [4]

Blaug does not provide one argument to substantiate his outrage. His chapter on Austrianism simply ends with that statement. Could it be that Blaug's and others' rejection of Mises's apriorism may have more to do with the fact that the demanding standards of argumentative rigor, which an apriorist methodology implies, prove too much for them? [5]

What led Mises to his characterization of economics as an a priori science? From the present day perspective it might be surprising to hear that Mises did not see his conception as out of line with the mainstream view prevailing in the early twentieth century. Mises did not wish to prescribe what economists should be doing as opposed to what they actually were doing. Rather, he saw his achievement as a philosopher of economics in systematizing, and in making explicit what economics really was, and how it had implicitly been conceived by almost everyone calling himself an economist.

And this is indeed the case. In giving a systematic explanation of what was formerly only implicit and unspoken knowledge, Mises did introduce some conceptual and terminological distinctions that had previously been unclear and unfamiliar, at least to the English-speaking world. But his position on the status of economics was essentially in full agreement with the then-orthodox view on the matter. They did not employ the term "a priori," but such mainstream economists as Jean Baptiste Say, Nassau Senior, and John E. Cairnes, for instance, described economics quite similarly.

Say writes: "A treatise on political economy will . . . be confined to the enunciation of a few general principles, not requiring even the support of proofs or illustrations; because these will be but the expression of what every one will know, arranged in a form convenient for comprehending them, as well as in their whole scope as in their relation to each other." And "political economy . . . whenever the principles which constitute its basis are the rigorous deductions of undeniable general facts, rests upon an immovable foundation." [6]

According to Nassau Senior, economic "premises consist of a few general propositions, the result of observations, or consciousness, and scarcely requiring proof, or even formal statement, which almost every man, as soon as he hears them, admits as familiar to his thoughts, or at least as included in his previous knowledge; and his inferences are nearly as general, and, if he has reasoned correctly, as certain as his premises." And economists should be "aware that the Science depends more on reasoning than on observation, and that its principal difficulty consists not in the ascertainment of its facts, but in the use of its terms." [7]

And John E. Cairnes remarks that while "mankind has no direct knowledge of ultimate physical principles" . . . "the economist starts with a knowledge of ultimate causes." . . . "The economist may thus be considered at the outset of his researches as already in possession of those ultimate principles governing the phenomena which form the subject of his study, the discovery of which in the case of physical investigation constitutes for the inquirer his most arduous task." "Conjecture [in economics] would manifestly be out of place, inasmuch as we possess in our consciousness and in the testimony of our senses . . . direct and easy proof of that which we desire to know. In Political Economy, accordingly, hypothesis is never used as a help toward the discovery of ultimate causes and laws." [8]

The views of Mises's predecessors, Menger, Böhm-Bawerk, and Wieser, are the same: They, too, describe economics as a discipline whose propositions can—in contrast to those of the natural sciences—be given some ultimate justification. Again, however, they do so without using the terminology employed by Mises. [9]

And finally, Mises's epistemological characterization of economics was also considered quite orthodox—and certainly not idiosyncratic, as Blaug would have it—after having been explicitly formulated by Mises. Lionel Robbins's book The Nature and Significance of Economic Science, which first appeared in 1932, is nothing but a somewhat watered-down version of Mises's description of economics as praxeology. Yet it was respected by the economics profession as the guiding methodological star for almost twenty years.

In fact, Robbins, in his Preface, explicitly singles out Mises as the most important source of his own methodological position. And Mises and Richard von Strigl—whose position is essentially indistinguishable from Mises's[10] —are cited approvingly in the text more often than anyone else. [11]

Yet, illuminating as all this may be for an assessment of the present-day situation, it is only history. What then is the rationale of the classical economists for regarding their science as different than the natural sciences? And what is behind Mises's explicit reconstruction of this difference as one between an a priori science and an aposteriori science? It was the recognition that the process of validation—the process of discovering whether some proposition is true or not—is different in one field of inquiry than in the other.

Let us first look briefly at the natural sciences. How do we know what the consequences will be if we subject some nature-given material to specified tests, let's say, if we mix it with another kind of material? Obviously we do not know before we actually try it and observe what happens. We can make a prediction, of course, but our prediction is only a hypothetical one, and observations are required to find out if we are right or wrong.

Moreover, even if we have observed some definite outcome, let's say that mixing the two materials leads to an explosion, can we then be sure that such an outcome will invariably occur whenever we mix such materials? Again, the answer is no. Our predictions will still, and permanently, be hypothetical. It is possible that an explosion will only result if certain other conditions—A, B, and C—are fulfilled. We can only find out whether or not this is the case and what these other conditions are by engaging in a never-ending trial and error process. This enables us to improve our knowledge progressively about the range of application for our original hypothetical prediction.

Now let us turn to some typical economic propositions. Consider the validation process of a proposition such as the following: Whenever two people A and B engage in a voluntary exchange, they must both expect to profit from it. And they must have reverse preference orders for the goods and services exchanged so that A values what he receives from B more highly than what he gives to him, and B must evaluate the same things the other way around.

Or consider this: Whenever an exchange is not voluntary but coerced, one party profits at the expense of the other.

Or the law of marginal utility: Whenever the supply of a good increases by one additional unit, provided each unit is regarded as of equal serviceability by a person, the value attached to this unit must decrease. For this additional unit can only be employed as a means for the attainment of a goal that is considered less valuable than the least valued goal satisfied by a unit of such good if the supply were one unit shorter.

Or take the Ricardian law of association: Of two producers, if A is more productive in the production of two types of goods than is B, they can still engage in a mutually beneficial division of labor. This is because overall physical productivity is higher if A specializes in producing one good which he can produce most efficiently, rather than both A and B producing both goods separately and autonomously.

Or as another example: Whenever minimum wage laws are enforced that require wages to be higher than existing market wages, involuntary unemployment will result.

Or as a final example: Whenever the quantity of money is increased while the demand for money to be held as cash reserve on hand is unchanged, the purchasing power of money will fall.

Considering such propositions, is the validation process involved in establishing them as true or false of the same type as that involved in establishing a proposition in the natural sciences? Are these propositions hypothetical in the same sense as a proposition regarding the effects of mixing two types of natural materials? Do we have to test these economic propositions continuously against observations? And does it require a never-ending trial and error process in order to find out the range of application for these propositions and to gradually improve our knowledge, such as we have seen to be the case in the natural sciences?

It seems quite evident—except to most economists for the last forty years—that the answer to these questions is a clear and unambiguous No. That A and B must expect to profit and have reverse preference orders follows from our understanding of what an exchange is. And the same is the case concerning the consequences of a coerced exchange. It is inconceivable that things could ever be different: It was so a million years ago and it will be so a million years hence. And the range of application for these propositions too is clear once and for all: They are true whenever something is a voluntary exchange or a coerced exchange, and that is all there is to it.

There is no difference with respect to the other examples given. That the marginal utility of additional units of supply of homogeneous goods must fall follows from the incontestable statement that every acting person always prefers what satisfies him more over what satisfies him less. It is simply absurd to think that continuous testing would be required to establish such a proposition.

The Ricardian law of association, along with a once-and-for-all delineation of its range of application, also logically follows from the very existence of the situation described. If A and B differ as described and accordingly there exists a technological substitution ratio for the goods produced (one such rate for A and one for B), then if they engage in a division of labor as characterized by the law, the physical output produced must be greater than it otherwise would be. Any other conclusion is logically flawed.

The same is true regarding the consequences of minimum wage laws or an increase in the quantity of money. An increase in unemployment and a decrease in the purchasing power of money are consequences which are logically implied in the very description of the initial condition as stated in the propositions at hand. As a matter of fact, it is absurd to regard these predictions as hypothetical and to think that their validity could not be established independently of observations, i.e., other than by actually trying out minimum wage laws or printing more money and observing what happens.

To use an analogy, it is as if one wanted to establish the theorem of Pythagoras by actually measuring sides and angles of triangles. Just as anyone would have to comment on such an endeavor, mustn't we say that to think economic propositions would have to be empirically tested is a sign of outright intellectual confusion?

But Mises by no means merely notices this rather obvious difference between economics and the empirical sciences. He makes us understand the nature of this difference and explains how and why a unique discipline like economics, which teaches something about reality without requiring observations, can possibly exist. It is this achievement of Mises's which can hardly be overrated.

In order to better understand his explanation, we must make an excursion into the field of philosophy, or more precisely into the field of the philosophy of knowledge or epistemology. In particular, we must examine the epistemology of Immanuel Kant as developed most completely in his Critique of Pure Reason. Mises's idea of praxeology is clearly influenced by Kant. This is not to say that Mises is a plain and simple Kantian. As a matter of fact, as I will point out later, Mises carries the Kantian epistemology beyond the point at which Kant himself left off. Mises improves the Kantian philosophy in a way that to this very day has been completely ignored and unappreciated by orthodox Kantian philosophers. Nonetheless, Mises takes from Kant his central conceptual and terminological distinctions as well as some fundamental Kantian insights into the nature of human knowledge. Thus we must turn to Kant.

Kant, in the course of his critique of classical empiricism, in particular that of David Hume, developed the idea that all our propositions can be classified in a two-fold way: On the one hand they are either analytic or synthetic, and on the other they are either a priori or a posteriori. The meaning of these distinctions is, in short, the following. Propositions are analytic whenever the means of formal logic are sufficient in order to find out whether they are true or not; otherwise propositions are synthetic ones. And propositions are a posteriori whenever observations are necessary in order to establish their truth or at least confirm them. If observations are not necessary, then propositions are a priori.

The characteristic mark of Kantian philosophy is the claim that true a priori synthetic propositions exist—and it is because Mises subscribes to this claim that he can be called a Kantian. Synthetic a priori propositions are those whose truth-value can be definitely established, even though in order to do so the means of formal logic are not sufficient (while, of course, necessary) and observations are unnecessary.

According to Kant, mathematics and geometry provide examples of true a priori synthetic propositions. Yet he also thinks that a proposition such as the general principle of causality—i.e., the statement that there are time-invariantly operating causes, and every event is embedded into a network of such causes—is a true synthetic a priori proposition.

I cannot go into great detail here to explain how Kant justifies this view. [12] A few remarks will have to suffice. First, how is the truth of such propositions derived, if formal logic is not sufficient and observations are unnecessary? Kant's answer is that the truth follows from self-evident material axioms.

What makes these axioms self-evident? Kant answers, it is not because they are evident in a psychological sense, in which case we would be immediately aware of them. On the contrary, Kant insists, it is usually much more painstaking to discover such axioms than it is to discover some empirical truth such as that the leaves of trees are green. They are self-evident because one cannot deny their truth without self-contradiction; that is, in attempting to deny them one would actually, implicitly, admit their truth.

How do we find such axioms? Kant answers, by reflecting upon ourselves, by understanding ourselves as knowing subjects. And this fact—that the truth of a priori synthetic propositions derives ultimately from inner, reflectively produced experience—also explains why such propositions can possibly have the status of being understood as necessarily true. Observational experience can only reveal things as they happen to be; there is nothing in it that indicates why things must be the way they are. Contrary to this, however, writes Kant, our reason can understand such things as being necessarily the way they are, "which it has itself produced according to its own design." [13]

In all this Mises follows Kant. Yet, as I said earlier, Mises adds one more extremely important insight that Kant had only vaguely glimpsed. It has been a common quarrel with Kantianism that this philosophy seemed to imply some sort of idealism. For if, as Kant sees it, true synthetic a priori propositions are propositions about how our mind works and must of necessity work, how can it be explained that such mental categories fit reality? How can it be explained, for instance, that reality conforms to the principle of causality if this principle has to be understood as one to which the operation of our mind must conform? Don't we have to make the absurd idealistic assumption that this is possible only because reality was actually created by the mind? So that I am not misunderstood, I do not think that such a charge against Kantianism is justified. [14] And yet, through parts of his formulations Kant has no doubt given this charge some plausibility.

Consider, for example, this programmatic statement of his: "So far it has been assumed that our knowledge had to conform to observational reality"; instead it should be assumed "that observational reality conform to our knowledge." [15]

Mises provides the solution to this challenge. It is true, as Kant says, that true synthetic a priori propositions are grounded in self-evident axioms and that these axioms have to be understood by reflection upon ourselves rather than being in any meaningful sense "observable." Yet we have to go one step further. We must recognize that such necessary truths are not simply categories of our mind, but that our mind is one of acting persons. Our mental categories have to be understood as ultimately grounded in categories of action. And as soon as this is recognized, all idealistic suggestions immediately disappear. Instead, an epistemology claiming the existence of true synthetic a priori propositions becomes a realistic epistemology. Since it is understood as ultimately grounded in categories of action, the gulf between the mental and the real, outside, physical world is bridged. As categories of action, they must be mental things as much as they are characteristics of reality. For it is through actions that the mind and reality make contact.

Kant had hinted at this solution. He thought mathematics, for instance, had to be grounded in our knowledge of the meaning of repetition, of repetitive operations. And he also realized, if only somewhat vaguely, that the principle of causality is implied in our understanding of what it is and means to act. [16]

Yet it is Mises who brings this insight to the foreground: Causality, he realizes, is a category of action. To act means to interfere at some earlier point in time in order to produce some later result, and thus every actor must presuppose the existence of constantly operating causes. Causality is a prerequisite of acting, as Mises puts it.

But Mises is not, as is Kant, interested in epistemology as such. With his recognition of action as the bridge between the mind and the outside reality, he has found a solution to the Kantian problem of how true synthetic a priori propositions can be possible. And he has offered some extremely valuable insights regarding the ultimate foundation of other central epistemological propositions besides the principle of causality, such as the law of contradiction as the cornerstone of logic. And he has thereby opened a path for future philosophical research that, to my knowledge, has hardly been traveled. Yet Mises's subject matter is economics, and so I will have to lay to rest the problem of explaining in more detail the causality principle as an a priori true proposition. [17]

Mises not only recognizes that epistemology indirectly rests on our reflective knowledge of action and can thereby claim to state something a priori true about reality but that economics does so too and does so in a much more direct way. Economic propositions flow directly from our reflectively gained knowledge of action; and the status of these propositions as a priori true statements about something real is derived from our understanding of what Mises terms "the axiom of action."

This axiom, the proposition that humans act, fulfills the requirements precisely for a true synthetic a priori proposition. It cannot be denied that this proposition is true, since the denial would have to be categorized as an action—and so the truth of the statement literally cannot be undone. And the axiom is also not derived from observation—there are only bodily movements to be observed but no such things as actions—but stems instead from reflective understanding.

Moreover, as something that has to be understood rather than observed, it is still knowledge about reality. This is because the conceptual distinctions involved in this understanding are nothing less than the categories employed in the mind's interaction with the physical world by means of its own physical body. And the axiom of action in all its implications is certainly not self-evident in a psychological sense, although once made explicit it can be understood as an undeniably true proposition about something real and existent. [18]

Certainly, it is not psychologically evident nor is it observable that with every action an actor pursues a goal; and that whatever the goal may be, the fact that it is pursued by an actor reveals that he places a relatively higher value on it than on any other goal of action he could conceive of at the start of his action.

It is neither evident nor observable that in order to achieve his most highly valued goal an action must interfere or decide not to interfere (which, of course, is also an interference) at an earlier point in time to produce some later result; nor that such interferences invariably imply the employment of some scarce means (at least those of the actor's body, its standing room and the time absorbed by the interference).

It is neither self-evident nor can it be observed that these means must also have value for an actor—a value derived from that of the goal—because the actor must regard their employment as necessary in order to effectively achieve the goal; and that actions can only be performed sequentially, always involving the making of a choice, i.e., taking up that one course of action which at some given point in time promises the most highly valued result to the actor and excluding at the same time the pursuit of other, less highly valued goals.

It is not automatically clear or observable that as a consequence of having to choose and give preference to one goal over another—of not being able to realize all goals simultaneously—each and every action implies the incurrence of costs. For example, forsaking the value attached to the most highly valued alternative goal that cannot be realized or whose realization must be deferred because the means necessary to effect it are bound up in the production of another, even more highly valued goal.

And lastly, it is not plainly evident or observable that at its starting point every goal of action must be considered worth more to the actor than its cost and capable of yielding a profit, i.e., a result whose value is ranked higher than that of the foregone opportunities. And yet, every action is also invariably threatened by the possibility of a loss if an actor finds, in retrospect, that the result actually achieved—contrary to previous expectations—has a lower value than the relinquished alternative would have had.

All of these categories—values, ends, means, choice, preference, cost, profit and loss, as well as time and causality—are implied in the axiom of action. Yet, that one is able to interpret observations in such categories requires that one already knows what it means to act. No one who is not an actor could ever understand them. They are not "given," ready to be observed, but observational experience is cast in these terms as it is construed by an actor. Nor is their reflective reconstruction a simple, psychologically self-evident intellectual task, as proved by a long line of abortive attempts along the way to the just-outlined insights into the nature of action.

It took painstaking intellectual effort to recognize explicitly what, once made explicit, everybody recognizes immediately as true and can understand as true synthetic a priori statements, i.e., propositions that can be validated independently of observations and thus cannot possibly be falsified by any observation whatsoever.

The attempt to disprove the action-axiom would itself be an action aimed at a goal, requiring means, excluding other courses of action, incurring costs, subjecting the actor to the possibility of achieving or not achieving the desired goal and so leading to a profit or a loss.

And the very possession of such knowledge then can never be disputed, and the validity of these concepts can never be falsified by any contingent experience, for disputing or falsifying anything would already have presupposed their very existence. As a matter of fact, a situation in which these categories of action would cease to have a real existence could itself never be observed, for making an observation, too, is an action.

Mises's great insight was that economic reasoning has its foundation in just this understanding of action; and that the status of economics as a sort of applied logic derives from the status of the action-axiom as an a priori-true synthetic proposition. The laws of exchange, the law of diminishing marginal utility, the Ricardian law of association, the law of price controls, and the quantity theory of money—all the examples of economic propositions which I have mentioned—can be logically derived from this axiom. And this is why it strikes one as ridiculous to think of such propositions as being of the same epistemological type as those of the natural sciences. To think that they are, and accordingly to require testing for their validation, is like supposing that we had to engage in some fact-finding process without knowing the possible outcome in order to establish the fact that one is indeed an actor. In a word: It is absurd.

Praxeology says that all economic propositions which claim to be true must be shown to be deducible by means of formal logic from the incontestably true material knowledge regarding the meaning of action. Specifically, all economic reasoning consists of the following:

(1) an understanding of the categories of action and the meaning of a change occurring in such things as values, preferences, knowledge, means, costs, etc;
(2) a description of a world in which the categories of action assume concrete meaning, where definite people are identified as actors with definite objects specified as their means of action, with some definite goals identified as values and definite things specified as costs. Such description could be one of a Robinson Crusoe world, or a world with more than one actor in which interpersonal relationships are possible; of a world of barter exchange or of money and exchanges that make use of money as a common medium of exchange; of a world of only land, labor, and time as factors of production, or a world with capital products; of a world with perfectly divisible or indivisible, specific or unspecific factors of production; or of a world with diverse social institutions, treating diverse actions as aggression and threatening them with physical punishment, etc; and
(3) a logical deduction of the consequences which result from the performance of some specified action within this world, or of the consequences which result for a specific actor if this situation is changed in a specified way.

Provided there is no flaw in the process of deduction, the conclusions that such reasoning yield must be valid a priori because their validity would ultimately go back to nothing but the indisputable axiom of action. If the situation and the changes introduced into it are fictional or assumptional (a Robinson Crusoe world, or a world with only indivisible or only completely specific factors of production), then the conclusions are, of course, a priori true only of such a "possible world." If, on the other hand, the situation and changes can be identified as real, perceived and conceptualized as such by real actors, then the conclusions are a priori true propositions about the world as it really is. [19]

Such is the idea of economics as praxeology. And such then is the ultimate disagreement that Austrians have with their colleagues: Their pronouncements cannot be deduced from the axiom of action or even stand in clear-cut contradiction to propositions that can be deduced from the axiom of action.

And even if there is agreement on the identification of facts and the assessment of certain events as being related to each other as causes and consequences, this agreement is superficial. For such economists falsely believe their statements to be empirically well-tested propositions when they are, in fact, propositions that are true a priori.

--------

[1] The first two essays are based on two lectures delivered at the Ludwig von Mises Institute's "Advanced Instructional Conference on Austrian Economics," June 21-27, 1987. The third essay is reprinted from The Economics and Ethics of Private Property (Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1993), pp. 141-64.

[2] Ludwig von Mises, Human Action , (Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1966), p.32

[3] Mises's methodological work is contained mainly in his Epistemological Problems of Economics (New York: New York University Press, 1981); Theory and History (Washington, D.C.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1985);The Ultimate Foundation of Economic Science (Kansas City, Kans.: sheed Andrews and McMeel, 1978); Human Action , Part I.

[4] Mark Blaug, The Methodology of Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980), p. 93; for a similar statement of outrage see Paul Samuelson, Collected Scientific Papers, vol. 3 (cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1972, p. 761.

[5] Another prominent critic of Praxeology is Terence W. Hutchison, The Significance and Basic Postulates of Economic Theory (London: Macmillan, 1938). Hutchison, like Blaug an adherent of the Popperian variant of empiricism, has since become much less enthusiastic about the prospects of advancing economics along empiricist lines (see, for instance, his Knowledge and Ignorance in Economics [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977; and The Politics and Philosophy of Economics [New York: New York University Press 1981]), yet he still sees no alternative to Popper's falsificationism. A position and development quite similar to Hutchison's is to be found in H. Albert (see his earlier Marktsoziologie und Entscheidungslogik (Neuwied: 1967). For a critique of the empiricist position, see Hans-Hermann Hoppe, Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung. Unterschungen zur Grundlegung von Soziologie und Ökonomie (Opladen: 1983); "Is Research Based on Causal Scientific Principles Possible in the Social Sciences?" Ratio 25, no. 1 (1983; "In Defense of Extreme Rationalism," [in .PDF] Review of Austrian Economics 3 (1988); "On Praxeology and the Praxeological Foundation of Epistemology and Ethics," in Llewellyn H. rockwell, Jr., ed., The Meaning of Ludwig von Mises (Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1989).

[6] Jean-Baptiste Say, Treatise on Political Economy (New York: Augustus Kelley, [1880] 1964, p. xx, xxvi.

[7] Nassau Senior, An Outline of the Science of Political Economy (New York: Augustus Kelley, [1836] 1965), pp. 2-3,5.

[8] John E. Cairnes, The Character and Logical Method of Political Economy (New York: Augustus Kelley, 1965), p. 83,87,89-90,95-96.

[9] See Carl Menger, Untersuchungen über die Methoden der Sozialwissenschaften (Leipzig: 1883); idem, Die Irrtümer des Historismus in der Deutschen Nationalökonomie (Wien: 1884); Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk, Schriften, F.X. Weiss, ed. (Vienna: 1924); Friedrich von Wieser, Theorie der gesellschaftlichen Wirtschaft (Tübingen: 1914); idem, Gesammelte Abhandlungen (Tübingen: 1929). For Mises's evaluation of his predecessors, see his Epistemological Problems of Economics, pp. 17-22. The term "a priori" in connection with economic theorems is also used by Frank H. Knight; his methodological writings, however, lack systematic rigor. See his "What Is Truth in Economics," in Knight, On the History and Method of Economics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956); and his "The Limitations of Scientific Method in Economics," in Knight, The Ethics of Competition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1935).

[10] Richard von Strigl, Die ökonomischen Kategorien und die Organisation der Wirtschaft (Jena: 1923).

[11] It may be worth mentioning that Robbin's methodological position, much like Friedrich A. Hayek's, became increasingly less Misesian over time due mainly to the influence of Karl R. Popper, their colleague at the London School of Economics. See on this Lionel Robbins, An Autobiography of an Economist (London: Macmillan, 1976); Hayek's disagreement with Mise's idea of praxeology has been most recently restated in his "Einleitung" to Ludwig von Mises's Erinnerungen (Stuttgart: 1978). Mises's own, entirely negative verdict on Popper can be found in his The Ultimate Foundation of Economic Science, p. 70. In support of this verdict see also Hans H. Hoppe Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung (Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag, 1983), pp. 48-49

[12] A brilliant interpretation and justification of Kant's a prioristic epistemology is to be found in F. Kambartel, Erfahrung und Struktur. Bausteine zu einer Kritik des Empirismus und Formalismus (Frankfurt/M.: 1968, esp. chapter 3; see also Hans-Hermann Hoppe, Handeln und Erkennen (Bern: 1976).

[13] Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, in Kant, Werke, vol. 2, W. Weischedel, ed. (Wiesbaden: 1956), p. 23.

[14] See in particular F. Kambartel's work cited in note 12; instructive is also the Kant interpretation given by the biologist-ethologist D. Lorenz, Vom Weltbild des Verhaltensforschers (Munich: 1964); idem, Die Rückseite des Spiegels, Versuch einer Naturgeschite menschlichen Erkennens (Munich: 1973). Among some followers of Austrianism, the Kant interpretation of Ayn Rand (see, for instance, her Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology (New York: New American Library, 1979); or For the New Intellectual (New York: Random House, 1961) enjoys great popularity. Her interpretation, replete with sweeping denunciatory pronouncements, however, is characterized by a complete absence of any interpretive documentation whatsoever. See, on Rand's arrogant ignorance regarding Kant, B. Goldberg, "Ayn Rand's 'For the New Intellectual'," New Individualist Review 1, no. 3 (1961).

[15] [Accidentally not included in this edition]

[16] For Kantian interpretations of mathematics see H. Dingler, Philosophie der Logik und Mathematik (Munich: 1931); Paul Lorenzen, Einführungin die operative Logik und Mathematik (Frankfurt/M.: 1970); Ludwig Wittgenstein, Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics (Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 1978); also Kambartel, Erfahrung und Struktur, pp. 118-22; for an unusually careful and cautious interpretation of Kantianism from the point of view of modern physics, see P. Mittelstaedt, Philosophische Probleme der modernen Physik (Nannheim: 1967).

[17] For some farther reaching considerations on these matters, see Hoppe "In Defense of Extreme Rationalism," Review of Austrian Economics 3 (1988).

[18] On this and the following see Mises, Human Action ,chapters IV,V.

[19] See also Hoppe, Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung, chapter 4.
__________________
I have seen all things that are done under the sun; all is vanity and a chase after wind.
Reply With Quote
  #2  
Cosmo Electrolux Cosmo Electrolux is offline
Stone Pants Rabbit
Cosmo Electrolux's Avatar
Join Date: May 2001
Location: In your distant memory
Cosmo Electrolux is probably a spambot
Old Aug 5th, 2005, 02:55 PM       
cliff notes, please.....
Reply With Quote
  #3  
The One and Only... The One and Only... is offline
Mocker
The One and Only...'s Avatar
Join Date: Jun 2003
Location: Harlem
The One and Only... is probably a spambot
Old Aug 5th, 2005, 03:07 PM       
The article establishes economics as a science rooted in a priori synthetic truths, credits Mises with overcoming the problem of idealism in Kantian philosophy by grounding mental categories of understanding in action, and tirades against a posteriori economics views.

I don't necessarily agree with all of it, but I found it intriguing.

Quote:
...Mises adds one more extremely important insight that Kant had only vaguely glimpsed. It has been a common quarrel with Kantianism that this philosophy seemed to imply some sort of idealism. For if, as Kant sees it, true synthetic a priori propositions are propositions about how our mind works and must of necessity work, how can it be explained that such mental categories fit reality? How can it be explained, for instance, that reality conforms to the principle of causality if this principle has to be understood as one to which the operation of our mind must conform? Don't we have to make the absurd idealistic assumption that this is possible only because reality was actually created by the mind? So that I am not misunderstood, I do not think that such a charge against Kantianism is justified. [14] And yet, through parts of his formulations Kant has no doubt given this charge some plausibility.

Consider, for example, this programmatic statement of his: "So far it has been assumed that our knowledge had to conform to observational reality"; instead it should be assumed "that observational reality conform to our knowledge." [15]

Mises provides the solution to this challenge. It is true, as Kant says, that true synthetic a priori propositions are grounded in self-evident axioms and that these axioms have to be understood by reflection upon ourselves rather than being in any meaningful sense "observable." Yet we have to go one step further. We must recognize that such necessary truths are not simply categories of our mind, but that our mind is one of acting persons. Our mental categories have to be understood as ultimately grounded in categories of action. And as soon as this is recognized, all idealistic suggestions immediately disappear. Instead, an epistemology claiming the existence of true synthetic a priori propositions becomes a realistic epistemology. Since it is understood as ultimately grounded in categories of action, the gulf between the mental and the real, outside, physical world is bridged. As categories of action, they must be mental things as much as they are characteristics of reality. For it is through actions that the mind and reality make contact.

Kant had hinted at this solution. He thought mathematics, for instance, had to be grounded in our knowledge of the meaning of repetition, of repetitive operations. And he also realized, if only somewhat vaguely, that the principle of causality is implied in our understanding of what it is and means to act. [16]

Yet it is Mises who brings this insight to the foreground: Causality, he realizes, is a category of action. To act means to interfere at some earlier point in time in order to produce some later result, and thus every actor must presuppose the existence of constantly operating causes. Causality is a prerequisite of acting, as Mises puts it.
__________________
I have seen all things that are done under the sun; all is vanity and a chase after wind.
Reply With Quote
  #4  
AChimp AChimp is offline
Resident Chimp
AChimp's Avatar
Join Date: Nov 2000
Location: The Jungles of Borneo
AChimp is probably a real personAChimp is probably a real person
Old Aug 5th, 2005, 03:48 PM       
I didn't read any of it, because I already know that it's crap.
Reply With Quote
  #5  
kellychaos kellychaos is offline
Mocker
 
Join Date: Feb 2003
Location: Where I Started But In A Different Place
kellychaos is probably a spambot
Old Aug 5th, 2005, 05:15 PM       
Quote:
How can it be explained, for instance, that reality conforms to the principle of causality if this principle has to be understood as one to which the operation of our mind must conform? Don't we have to make the absurd idealistic assumption that this is possible only because reality was actually created by the mind?
How about the fact that your brain, in early childhood, was developing at a rapid rate and being sculpted in ways which you will never remember or understand? How can you honestly say that you remember events or thoughts before the age of 3 or so? Who's to say WHEN this development took place? Perhaps, at least, the matrix/or framework for thinking causually WAS a priori. You don't know, I don't know and SHE doesn't know ... i.e. shut up.
__________________

Wherever you go, there you are.
Reply With Quote
  #6  
ziggytrix ziggytrix is offline
Mocker
ziggytrix's Avatar
Join Date: Mar 2003
Location: i come from the water
ziggytrix is probably a spambot
Old Aug 5th, 2005, 06:19 PM       
mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental mental
__________________
BOYCOTT SIGNATURES!
Reply With Quote
  #7  
Emu Emu is offline
Level 29 ♂
Emu's Avatar
Join Date: Aug 2003
Location: Peoria, IL
Emu is probably a real personEmu is probably a real person
Old Aug 5th, 2005, 07:09 PM       
Reply With Quote
  #8  
The One and Only... The One and Only... is offline
Mocker
The One and Only...'s Avatar
Join Date: Jun 2003
Location: Harlem
The One and Only... is probably a spambot
Old Aug 6th, 2005, 02:28 AM       
You motherfuckers.

Look, the point is that mainstream economics is horribly flawed in that it is based on an a posteriori foundation. In truth, praxeology is a far more viable option for economic science.
__________________
I have seen all things that are done under the sun; all is vanity and a chase after wind.
Reply With Quote
  #9  
Helm Helm is offline
Mocker
 
Join Date: Feb 2003
Location: Mount Fuji
Helm is probably a spambot
Old Aug 6th, 2005, 05:31 AM       
what ziggy said
__________________
Reply With Quote
  #10  
Cosmo Electrolux Cosmo Electrolux is offline
Stone Pants Rabbit
Cosmo Electrolux's Avatar
Join Date: May 2001
Location: In your distant memory
Cosmo Electrolux is probably a spambot
Old Aug 6th, 2005, 08:33 AM       
Quote:
Originally Posted by AChimp
I didn't read any of it, because I already know that it's crap.
I wanted to see what it was about before investing THAT much time.
Reply With Quote
  #11  
Emu Emu is offline
Level 29 ♂
Emu's Avatar
Join Date: Aug 2003
Location: Peoria, IL
Emu is probably a real personEmu is probably a real person
Old Aug 6th, 2005, 11:29 AM       
Quote:
Originally Posted by The One and Only...
Look, the point is that economics is horribly flawed in that it is based on an foundation. In truth, is a far more option for economic science.
SEE, IF YOUT AKE OUT THE BUZZ WORDS HE'S LOST, MAN!!!13GJK
Reply With Quote
  #12  
The One and Only... The One and Only... is offline
Mocker
The One and Only...'s Avatar
Join Date: Jun 2003
Location: Harlem
The One and Only... is probably a spambot
Old Aug 6th, 2005, 12:59 PM       
A posteriori - After experience; truth derived from observations.

Praxeology - The science of human action.
__________________
I have seen all things that are done under the sun; all is vanity and a chase after wind.
Reply With Quote
  #13  
Emu Emu is offline
Level 29 ♂
Emu's Avatar
Join Date: Aug 2003
Location: Peoria, IL
Emu is probably a real personEmu is probably a real person
Old Aug 6th, 2005, 01:21 PM       
Unfortunately, I know what those words mean. I'm just saying that you're a pretentious dick for using those words.
Reply With Quote
  #14  
kellychaos kellychaos is offline
Mocker
 
Join Date: Feb 2003
Location: Where I Started But In A Different Place
kellychaos is probably a spambot
Old Aug 6th, 2005, 01:29 PM       
I knew that a priori.
__________________

Wherever you go, there you are.
Reply With Quote
  #15  
KevinTheOmnivore KevinTheOmnivore is offline
Mocker
KevinTheOmnivore's Avatar
Join Date: Feb 2003
Location: Brooklyn, NY
KevinTheOmnivore is probably a spambot
Old Aug 6th, 2005, 04:04 PM       
That's OAO, "Blowing up the Ivory Tower, one elitist at a time."

Reply With Quote
  #16  
The One and Only... The One and Only... is offline
Mocker
The One and Only...'s Avatar
Join Date: Jun 2003
Location: Harlem
The One and Only... is probably a spambot
Old Aug 7th, 2005, 11:34 AM       
I should explain exactly what I mean by that.

To me, the Ivory Tower represents a monopoly on intellectualism maintained by an elitist establishment. I think that everyone should become an intellectual; that there should be no monopoly, and no elite.
__________________
I have seen all things that are done under the sun; all is vanity and a chase after wind.
Reply With Quote
  #17  
Emu Emu is offline
Level 29 ♂
Emu's Avatar
Join Date: Aug 2003
Location: Peoria, IL
Emu is probably a real personEmu is probably a real person
Old Aug 7th, 2005, 12:05 PM       
If everyone is an intellectual, then what is intellectualism? You commie.
Reply With Quote
  #18  
theapportioner theapportioner is offline
Mocker
theapportioner's Avatar
Join Date: Feb 2003
theapportioner is probably a spambot
Old Aug 7th, 2005, 11:27 PM       
It is an interesting article. Although, I find it odd that Mises calls economics the science of human action since a priori statements don't require human existence at all for them to be valid. Personally, I'd rather look to psychology, or better yet, cognitive neuroscience, for an explanation of human action.
Reply With Quote
  #19  
The One and Only... The One and Only... is offline
Mocker
The One and Only...'s Avatar
Join Date: Jun 2003
Location: Harlem
The One and Only... is probably a spambot
Old Aug 8th, 2005, 12:03 AM       
Well actually, the article defines it as "the logic of action," but it is commonly understood/applied to the action of human beings (see the definition given here).

As far as psychology goes, they are very different doctrines - psychology would attempt to find the causes of human action; praxeology looks at the logistics of it. Psychology might be able to determine why a human acts in a certain way, but praxeology establishes the univeral rules which humans must act under.

To me, these axioms are true due to the logical consequences of the very definitions of the words involved. That both parties must benefit from a voluntary exchange is axiomatic, because no one would engage in such an exchange without benefitting (albeit this is a simplified version - one must discount fraud and put "benefit" in a certain context).
__________________
I have seen all things that are done under the sun; all is vanity and a chase after wind.
Reply With Quote
  #20  
theapportioner theapportioner is offline
Mocker
theapportioner's Avatar
Join Date: Feb 2003
theapportioner is probably a spambot
Old Aug 8th, 2005, 12:18 AM       
Fair enough. Though I wonder how far you can take praxeology beyond the very basics. The endeavor reminds me of logical positivism, which as we all know didn't work out so well.
Reply With Quote
  #21  
theapportioner theapportioner is offline
Mocker
theapportioner's Avatar
Join Date: Feb 2003
theapportioner is probably a spambot
Old Aug 8th, 2005, 12:51 AM       
Here's an interesting read for you, OAO:

WVO Quine: Two dogmas of empiricism.

http://www.ditext.com/quine/quine.html
Reply With Quote
  #22  
The One and Only... The One and Only... is offline
Mocker
The One and Only...'s Avatar
Join Date: Jun 2003
Location: Harlem
The One and Only... is probably a spambot
Old Aug 8th, 2005, 02:38 AM       
I've gotten through the first two parts so far.

Long ago I yielded that imperfect communication exists within language, and I actually feel that a new language is necessary (or at least desireable) for philosophical discourse a la the "primitive notation" model. This is why I stress that any sort of system based upon the necessary consequences of definitions must always be contextually evaluated and at times modified to keep in line with the original conceptualization. In addition, the problem of linguistics is no more damning to these analytic systems than to those relying on observation, for there is just as much room for error in translating experience into words as there is concepts - and at their roots, concepts are what words truly represent.

I guess, then, a priori truths are more the results of concepts than actual definition... ah, well. You get where I'm going with this. I'll try to finish the article sometime when it isn't 2 AM.
__________________
I have seen all things that are done under the sun; all is vanity and a chase after wind.
Reply With Quote
  #23  
Dole Dole is offline
Mocker
Dole's Avatar
Join Date: Jun 2003
Location: Brighton & Motherfucking Hove
Dole is probably a spambot
Old Aug 8th, 2005, 09:33 AM       
My view has always been if everyone just loved each other, there would be no war and stuff.
__________________
I don't get it. I mean, why did they fuck with the formula? Where are the car songs? There's only one song about surfing and it's a downer!
Reply With Quote
Reply



Posting Rules
You may not post new threads
You may post replies
You may not post attachments
You may not edit your posts

vB code is On
Smilies are On
[IMG] code is On
HTML code is Off
Forum Jump

   


All times are GMT -4. The time now is 03:31 PM.


© 2008 I-Mockery.com
Powered by: vBulletin
Copyright ©2000 - 2024, Jelsoft Enterprises Ltd.